Guest post: "Are classical, deterministic, field theories compatible with the predictions of quantum mechanics?"
Elliptic Composability is a blog dedicated to quantum mechanics and a recent post attracted a lot of attention and comments. In particular one of the readers, Andrei, has argued for classical physics and we have engaged in a lot of back and forth discussions about it. Although I disagree with Andrei, I have found his arguments well constructed and I thought my debate with him would be of interest to a much larger audience. So I have invited Andrei to present his best arguments in a guest post to which I will present my counter-arguments in the next post.
Without further ado, here is Andrei's guest post:
Thank you, Florin , for inviting me to
present on your blog my arguments that classical physics can still play a role
in understanding nature.
The following objections are usually raised against the
search for classical explanations for quantum phenomena:
Objection 1: Classical, local
theories have been ruled out by Bell ’s
theorem.
Objection 2: Classical theories
cannot explain single-particle interference (double slit experiment), quantum tunneling,
the stability of atoms or energy quantification in atoms or molecules.
Objection 3: Even if one could
elude the previous points, there is no reason to pursue classical theories
because quantum mechanics perfectly predicts all observed phenomena.
Objection 1
It is a widespread belief that Bell ’s
theorem rules out local realism. As classical field theories are both local and
realistic they couldn’t possible reproduce the predictions of quantum
mechanics. However, a more careful reading of the theorem would be:
Assuming the experimenters are
free to choose what measurements to perform, the logical conclusion is that no
local and realistic theory can reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics.
One can easily notice that, if the
motion of quantum particles (including the particles the experimenter himself
is made of) is described by some classical, deterministic, field theory, this
freedom of choice does not make any sense.
Classical determinism implies that certain past configuration uniquely
determines the future. Anything else would require a violation of the physical
law.
One can still object that, even if
the experimenters (say Bob and Alice) follow some deterministic process there
is still no reason to assume that their behavior would be correlated. Alice
could use the decay of some radioactive material to decide the measurement she
performs, while Bob could let his measurement be decided by very complex random
number generation software. Any assumed correlation between such unrelated
processes would amount to a conspiracy no one should seriously consider.
Let’s analyze however, this
experiment from the point of view of a classical field theory. One can make the
following two observations:
a. the
experiment reduces, at microscopic scale, to three groups of particles: A
(Alice, her radioactive material and the detector she controls), B (Bob, his
computer and the detector he controls), S (the source of the entangled
particles).
b. The
trajectory of a particle in A would be a function of position/momenta of
particles in A,B and C; the trajectory of a particle in B would be a function
of position/momenta of particles in A,B and C; The trajectory of a particle in
C would be a function of position/momenta of particles in A,B and C
From (a) and (b) it follows that Alice
and Bob (and the source of the entangled particles), cannot be independent of
one another. The so-called conspiracy is a direct consequence of the
mathematical structure of a classical field theory.
In conclusion I have proven that Bell ’s
theorem cannot rule out classical deterministic field theories.
Objection 2
I will show here how some “mysterious”
quantum effects are not in contradiction with what one would expect if some
classical field theory describes the motion of particles at the fundamental
level. I will start with the iconic double-slit experiment as it is presented
by Feynman here:
Feynman says:
“In this chapter we shall tackle
immediately the basic element of the mysterious behavior in its most strange
form. We choose to examine a phenomenon which is impossible, absolutely impossible, to explain in
any classical way, and which has in it the heart of quantum mechanics. In
reality, it contains the only
mystery. We cannot make the mystery go away by “explaining” how it works.”
I invite everyone to read the
whole description of the experiment there. Feynman chooses to use indestructible bullets as the classic
analogs of electrons. The experiment is performed with the first slit open,
then with the second slit open, and, in the end, with both slits open. The
expected result is:
“The probabilities just add
together. The effect with both holes open is the sum of the effects with each
hole open alone. We shall call this result an observation of “no interference,” for a reason that you
will see later. So much for bullets. They come in lumps, and their probability
of arrival shows no interference.”
This is all nice, but classical
physics is not the same thing as Newtonian physics of the rigid body. Let’s
consider a better classical approximation of the electron, a charged bullet.
The slits are made of some material that will necessarily contain a large
number of charged “bullets”. As the test bullet travels, its trajectory will be
determined by the field generated by the slitted barrier. The field will be a
function of position/momenta of the “bullets” in the barrier. But the field
produced by a barrier with two slits will be different than the field produced
by a barrier with only one slit, so the effect with both holes open is NOT the
sum of the effects with each hole open alone.
In this paper:
Yves Couder has provided
experimental confirmation for classical single-particle interference. The
greatest mystery of quantum mechanics has been solved by the good old classical
field theory.
Let’s move to another “classical
impossibility”: stable atoms with quantified energy levels. It is claimed that
classical electrodynamics cannot account for stable atoms, and I would accept
this claim, even if the situation is not as clear as it seems. For a possible
counterexample I recommend this:
The author, Gryziński, has
published its model in top peer-reviewed
magazines so I guess there is some truth about it.
But, for the sake of the argument,
let’s assume that classical electrodynamics cannot explain the atom. Does it
prove that no classical theory could do it? I don’t think so. We know that
stable groups of charges with well-defined energies are possible. They are
called ionic crystals. The charged particles do not move (if thermal motion is
ignored), so there is no energy loss by radiation. The geometry of the crystal
dictates the energy, which has a well-defined value. The reason for the
stability of the crystals stays in the repulsive force generated by the
orbiting electrons. One can argue that electrons are not composite particles,
but a repulsive force can be provided by some modification of the electric
field.
The third example I will discuss
here is tunneling. Presumably, classical physics cannot explain this phenomenon
because the particle does not have enough energy to overcome the barrier.
There
are two observations I can make for this case:
a. Neither
the energy of the particle that tunnels, nor the value of the potential are
accurately known at the moment of tunneling. They are average values, and these
can be very different from the instantaneous ones.
b. The
actual force acting on the particle depends on the classical theory used to
describe the experiment. A new theory could predict a much stronger force.
Objection 3
In the end I would like to point
out a few reasons for investigating classical theories.
a. If
nature is not probabilistic after all, there is much to be discovered. Detailed
mechanism behind quantum phenomena should be revealed, bringing out a deeper
understanding of our universe, and maybe new physical effects.
b. Quantum
theories are not well equipped to describe the universe as a whole. There is no
observer outside the universe, no measurement can be performed on it, not even
in principle.
c. Due
to its inability to provide an objective description of reality, quantum
mechanics may not be able to solve the cosmological constant problem. A theory
that states clearly “what’s there” could provide a much better estimate of the
vacuum energy. After all we are not interested in what energy someone could
find by performing a measurement on the vacuum, but what the vacuum consists of,
when no one is there to pump energy into it.
d. Quantum
mechanics requires an infinitely large instrument to measure a variable with
infinite precision. When gravity is taken into account, it follows that local, perfectly
defined properties cannot exist, because, beyond a certain mass, the instrument
would collapse into a black hole.
For a detailed description of the latter two points, please
read this paper by Nima Arkani-Hamed:
Thanks again, Florin , for this
opportunity to present my arguments, and I am looking forward to seeing your opinion
about them.
Andrei
Holy cow.
ReplyDeleteI will rebut point for point Andrei in the next post. Hence I will not do it in the commenting section here. But feel free to argue with him as well.
DeleteIn the meantime I do have a question for you. You keep mentioning some religious videos about QM and you said they are well constructed . However you did not say if they are correct or not. Do you agree with their scientific claims?
Dear Florin, I do not "keep on mentioning" them. I mentioned them twice or thrice in my life. Their claims are of philosophical character so describing them as "scientific claims" may be a distortion. But yes, if one carefully tries to understand the videos as scientific claims, almost all of them are basically correct. Surely the percentage of the correct ones is vastly higher than on your blog.
DeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteIt's about superdeteminism in this guest post?
ReplyDeleteDear Calin,
DeleteYou may call it that, but I think this term is redundant, because determinism, at least in the context of field theories, has the same implications (no free will, no independence of distant systems, etc.).
For theories like Newtonian mechanics of the rigid bodies, where you only have interactions by elastic collisions, determinism may allow distant systems to be independent. If you want them to be correlated, this correlation has to be put by hand in the initial conditions. This is probably the reason super determinism is rejected as conspiracy.
In field theories no conspiracy is required. Correlations are a direct consequence of the fact that the local value of the field (which determines the trajectory of the test particle) depends on the state of all other particles (as long as those particles are sources for the field).
Andrei
But we don't have such a dependence, we can't construct a totally deterministic theory. In superdeterminism there isn't a theory from where we can deduct the values of an observable. They are determined, but determined by nothing we can conceive of.
DeleteI do not understand your point. What's wrong with a totally deterministic theory?
DeleteLet's assume, for the sake of the argument, that the fundamental theory describing the motion of particles is classical electrodynamics. So, all matter (electrons, protons - ignore internal structure of protons, other particles, gravity, etc.) move according to this theory. What is the problem with the observables?
Andrei
We cannot deduce from anywhere the actual values that an observable will take (even in principle, only the probability), so, actually, we don't have a deterministic THEORY, only, in a best case, a deterministic universe with no theory at all (this is what I understand that is superdeterminism). Probably Florin will explain it more clearly
DeleteSo, according to this line of reasoning, if classical electrodynamics wouldn't have failed in explaining atomic spectra, photoelectric effect, etc. we would be in a situation of not having a theory at all. Would you agree with this?
Deleteif classical electrodynamics would explain atomic spectra and all, we could exactly predict the values of the observables, not probabilisticaly
ReplyDeleteIn order to make exact predictions you need:
ReplyDelete1. The equations of motion (provided by the deterministic theory)
2. Initial conditions
If, for some reason or another you cannot find out the initial conditions you will be unable to make exact predictions. Why should this invalidate the theory?
Andrei
I think that we have situation in which we could know the initial conditions with arbitrary exact precision and we cannot make arbitrary exact predictions
ReplyDeleteCan you describe in detail such a situation?
DeleteAndrei
a simple double slits experiment
ReplyDeleteA double slit experiment involves about 10^25 particles from the barrier and screen. The trajectory of the incoming particle is a function of the field produced by them. The initial conditions in this case are represented by the position/momenta of all those particles, about 6 x 10^25 numbers. It seems unlikely that you can know all those variables with arbitrary precision (uncertainty principle might be a problem) and keep them constant during the experiment.
DeleteAndrei
If the results would depend heavily on those numbers you say, we wouldn't see a nice interference pattern.
ReplyDeleteThe exact trajectory depends on those numbers; the interference pattern is a statistical effect. Anyway, you don't know even the initial state of the test particle because of uncertainty principle.
DeleteAndrei
I think Florin responded more clearly in his new post
DeleteAll the best,
Calin
I think Florin responded more clearly in his new post
DeleteAll the best,
Calin