Solving Hilbert’s sixth problem
The fundamental relationship between ontology and dynamic
Last time we have derived the Leibnitz identity which is the
root cause for information conservation in nature (from this one can derive
unitarity in quantum mechanics for example). How does Leibnitz identity hold
under tensor composition?
The quantum reconstruction argument is categorical, meaning
it is naturally expressed in terms of category theory but whenever possible we will stress a more physical point of view. So now let
us introduce a composability category U(⊗,R, ρ,…) where ⊗ is the tensor product
which combines two physical systems A and B into a larger system: A⊗B. As an example, A⊗B
could be a hydrogen atom, where A is the electron, and B is the proton.
R represents the
real number field and we pick R over
any other mathematical field because we want to be able to compute probabilities in the usual way. ρ,… belong to our unspecified set of
local operations {o}. This composability category has as the identity element
the chosen field R (U⊗R = R⊗U = U) and elements of R will be understood
as arbitrary constant functions.
Now we can
see how ρ
acts on a constant function 1. Using the Leibnitz
identity:
f ρ 1 = f ρ (1 x 1) = (f ρ 1) x
1 + 1 x (f ρ 1) = 2x (f ρ 1)
and so we have in general that f ρ1 = 0 for
any function f. (This is very natural, we just stated in a fancy abstract way
that the derivation of a constant function is zero)
Using the tensor product and using the unit of the
composability category we have:
(f ⊗1) ρ12 (g ⊗1) = (f ρ g) ⊗1 = (f ρ g)
where ρ12 is the bipartite product
ρ.
The bipartite (and in general the n-partite) products must
be build out of the available products in {o}. If in our universe of discourse the collection {o} of the available
products contains only the product ρ we have:
. (f ⊗1) ρ12 (g ⊗1) = (f ρ g) ⊗(1 ρ 1) = 0 because (1 ρ 1) = 0
Hence the ρ product is trivial
if it exists by itself. There must exists at least another product θ to
have an interesting domain. If ρ corresponds to the dynamic θ
corresponds to ontology (observables).
Suppose that {o} contains only ρ and
θ. The bipartite products ρ12 and θ12
must be constructed out of ρ and θ. The most general way for
this is as follows:
(f1 ⊗ f2)ρ12(g1 ⊗ g2) = a(f1ρ
g1) ⊗ (f2ρ
g2) +b(f1ρ g1) ⊗ (f2θ g2)
+ c(f1θ g1) ⊗ (f2ρ g2) + d(f1θ g1)
⊗ (f2θ g2)
(f1 ⊗ f2) θ 12(g1 ⊗ g2) = x(f1ρ
g1) ⊗ (f2ρ
g2) +y(f1ρ g1) ⊗ (f2θ g2)
+ z(f1θ g1) ⊗ (f2ρ g2) + w(f1θ g1)
⊗ (f2θ g2)
In shorthand
notation:
Rho_12 = a rho_1 rho_2 + b rho_1 theta_2 + c
theta_1 rho_2 + d theta_1 theta_2
Theta_12 =
x rho_1 rho_2 + y rho_1 theta_2 + z
theta_1 rho_2 + w theta_1 theta_2
Now the
goal is to determine the values of the parameters a,b,c,d,x,y,z,w. Since the
relationship is general, we can pick f1 =f2 = 1 and we can use the identity: 1 rho
g = 0;
Then in
the first relationship only c and d terms survive. If we normalize Theta
such that (1 theta 1) = 1 this demands c=1 and d=0. Similarly z=0, w = 1. Using
the same trick with g1 = g 2 = 1
demands b=1 y=0
So we must
have:
(f1 ⊗ f2)ρ12(g1 ⊗ g2) = a(f1ρ
g1) ⊗ (f2ρ
g2) +(f1ρ g1) ⊗ (f2θ g2)
+ (f1θ g1) ⊗ (f2ρ g2)
(f1 ⊗ f2) θ 12(g1 ⊗ g2) = x(f1ρ
g1) ⊗ (f2ρ
g2) + (f1θ g1) ⊗ (f2θ g2)
The a term can be eliminated by applying the
Leibnitz identity on itself on the bipartite products ρ12. Therefore
the fundamental composability relation becomes:
ρ12 = ρ⊗θ + θ⊗ρ
θ 12 = θ⊗θ + xρ⊗ρ
where x
could be normalized to be +1, 0, -1.
The three
possible parameters -1, 0, 1 corresponds to “fixed points” in a categorical
(composability) theory and they correspond to (this remains to be shown):
-quantum
mechanics (elliptical composability)
-classical
mechanics (parabolic composability)
-split-complex
(hyperbolic) quantum mechanics (hyperbolic composability)
If Theta
represents the algebra of observables and Alice and Bob form a bipartite system
(EPR pair), x=0 means that the observables
are separable. x != 0 means that the observables are affected by the dynamics
and the system can be entangled!!!
We can normalize
x to be +1,0,-1, but if we do preserve the dimensions, when it is not zero, x =
+/- ħ2/4.
Invariance
of the laws of nature under composability demands that x remains the same or,
equivalently that the Plank constant is the same for all quantum systems!
Now for
some references.
The core
ideas were developed by Emile Grgin and Aage Petersen at Yeshiva University in
the 70s (Aage Petersen was Bohr’s assistant and Bohr had the hunch that
classical and quantum mechanics share core features beyond the correspondence
principle)
The idea
that composability demands the invariance of the Plank constant was developed by
Sahoo, a colleague of Grgin: http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0301044
Expanding
on Grgin’s original idea I wrote: http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.3935
which was uploaded on the archive only 11 days before a similar result by Anton
Kapustin of Caltech: http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.6917
Kapustin’s paper had the same old Grgin paper for inspiration and is written in the category
theory formulation. We worked independently and the papers are about 80%
identical in content notwithstanding that they look very different. Eliminating
(correctly and conclusively) the hyperbolic composability class was done in http://arxiv.org/abs/1311.6461 and
his lead to a major generalization of functional analysis (I’ll cover this in
subsequent posts). There are still more unpublished results.
If the
reader is interested into an excellent reference for classical and quantum
mechanics (which includes the Lie-Jordan algebraic formulation of quantum
mechanics) I highly recommend Nicolas Landsman’s book: http://www.amazon.com/Mathematical-Classical-Mechanics-Monographs-Mathematics/dp/038798318X
Tweet
Tweet
No comments:
Post a Comment